-->
Who but a
philosopher would ask a nerdy question like that? You know a question is nerdy
when you try to answer it in your own regular-guy way. Say I, on my way to the
marriage couch, am asked if I think my adding to the population of the earth is
ethical. I'm stumped. "How does ethics get into it?" I wonder.
"Here's
how," says Christine Overall, the first of three philosophers to speak in
recent books (reviewed in the New Yorker,
4-9-12). "Your decision to have a child, generalized for your species,
will, through either over-population or under-population, affect the happiness
of all future children. Decisions that affect the happiness of others are
ethical decisions" (extracted from the review).
Overall
stimulates and expands my thinking, as regular guys count on nerds to do. I hadn't thought about the
over-population problem at all, at least with respect to my personal
"decision." And over-population is just one of procreation's hazards.
David Benatar ("Better Never to Have Been: The Harm of Coming Into
Existence") shows me, through an argument I can almost follow, "that
a life filled with good and containing only the most minute quantity of bad — a
life of utter bliss adulterated only by the pain of a single pinprick — is
worse than no life at all." My child could arrive in a one-pin paradise and
still be worse off than if he hadn't been born.
Put Overall with
Benatar and I'm thrown into a stew. Overall has taught me that I am ethically
responsible for human beings that go onto any kind of planet. Benatar wants me
to consider the candidates for occupancy of that planet, none of whom are born
yet. Overall, I remember, said that "non-existent people have no moral
standing." Does that take the "ethical" out of my choice? There
I am, in the stew expert philosophers throw you in.
Now I think the
better a reviewer (or teacher, or forum-presider) is at bringing philosophers
together the hotter the stew is going to be and the more quickly you're going
to be in it. With this reviewer, Elizabeth Kolbert, I get flame after flame and
by the time the third philosopher, Bryan Caplan, enters I am really feeling the
heat. Like the others Caplan thinks that "people need to think more
seriously about the decision to have children." Seriousness to him, an
economics professor, means careful, realistic calculation. You can see him at
the board, drawing a graph. On the age scale his "pleasant number"
(of children, for parents' pleaure) rises from one in the third decade of life
to five in the seventh and beyond. He smoothes the curve, stands back, rubs his
chin, checks with the class, and, for the rich, full life, goes for three.
(While Kolbert, in the back of the room, bless her, is explaining to another
regular babe that "kids are a pain in the ass when they're small.")
Ah, but there's a hand. The over-population problem? Not to worry. "More
people mean more ideas, the fuel of progress," says Professor Caplan.
It's hard to go
deeply into an attractive subject without getting nerdy about it, I know, and
English professors can be as nerdy as anybody, but their subject does do
something for them that philosophy and economics just don't seem to do for
these professors. It keeps them, through poems and stories, in touch with real
life, messy life, the life regular people live. It's the life Overall and
Benatar leave behind when they examine the claim that having a child will
benefit (or harm) future generations. Regular people don't make such claims.
Overall and Benatar are looking at graduate students around a seminar table.
Apprentice nerds.
I know, they're
doing that for the benefit of regular people, showing them how to "think
more rigorously about the decision to have children" (Caplan) and that
"morally rigorous analysis" (Overall) is what professors of ethics
teach. I know that that's what academics generally do, teach rigor to the
slack, and that it has many benefits. But it's often false to the real world,
as it is here.
In the real world
people can't see into the future clearly, and they, most of them, know it. So
when a professor asks them, "Is
procreation immoral?" (or, in their terms, "Is what I am about to do
on the couch ethical?") they say something like this: "I know that
there could be harm or benefit in what I am about to do but I just can't see
how it will come. It's too far in the future and I don't have time to study it
that much. So I'll leave it up to those responsible and the experts who advise
them. They are my best guide. If they decide, when the time comes, that it's
good for citizens to have or not have children I'll probably go along. In the
meantime I'm not going to worry about it. I have too much else to worry
about."
Stories and poems
show how much else there is to worry about and how limited we are in dealing
with it. They provide a constant correction to our tendencies to simplify and
to over-presume — tendencies that appear clearly in the philosophers Kolbert
has chosen. There's Caplan, reducing the good life to graphable numbers, there's
Benatar removing common sense from his planet populators, there's Overall
trusting a poll to gauge happiness, trusting happiness as a category. And there
are all three, trusting that the human mind can adequately deal with these
problems.
Poets show how complicated
the problems are and some poets, older ones, show how foolish (or tragic) men
can be if they presume that they have the power to solve them. Dante and Milton
thought that presumption a sin, and had a name for it: intellectual pride.
This is not to
set poets against philosophers. John Locke and John Milton warn against
presumption in almost the same terms. Milton's finally wise Adam has learned
that
not to know at large
of things remote
From use,
obscure and subtle, but to know
That which before
us lies in daily life,
Is the prime
Wisdom.
Some things you have to leave to
God, the angel Raphael has told him. "Be lowly wise."
That's just what
Locke is saying, in philosopher's language:
Whereas,
were the capacities of our understandings well considered, the extent of our
knowledge once discovered, and the horizon found which sets the bounds between
the enlightened and dark parts of things; between what is and what is not
comprehensible by us, men would perhaps with less scruple acquiesce in the
avowed ignorance of the one, and employ their thoughts and discourse with more
advantage and satisfaction in the other.
Does Locke's nearby introduction of
God, doing just what Milton's God does (giving mankind all they need for a good
daily life), reduce the weight of this for contemporary philosophers? Will it
do the same for their students, philosophy majors? I mean, who on campus is better at doubting the existence of
God?
If that's the
case I think teachers and forum-organizers need to add more English majors to
their stew. Since God fills most of what they read English majors have learned
to separate questions of his wisdom from questions of his existence, and here
questions of God's existence are clearly a distraction. It's wisdom we're after.
No comments:
Post a Comment